Skip to main content

The Material Theory of Induction: Contents

The Material Theory of Induction
Contents
    • Notifications
    • Privacy
  • Project HomeThe Material Theory of Induction
  • Projects
  • Learn more about Manifold

Notes

Show the following:

  • Annotations
  • Resources
Search within:

Adjust appearance:

  • font
    Font style
  • color scheme
  • Margins
table of contents
  1. Front Matter
    1. Series
    2. Title Page
    3. Copyright
  2. Preface
  3. Contents
  4. Prolog
  5. The Material Theory of Induction Stated and Illustrated
  6. What Powers Inductive Inference?
  7. Replicability of Experiment
  8. Analogy
  9. Epistemic Virtues and Epistemic Values: A Skeptical Critique
  10. Simplicity as a Surrogate
  11. Simplicity in Model Selection
  12. Inference to the Best Explanation: The General Account
  13. Inference to the Best Explanation: Examples
  14. Why Not Bayes
  15. Circularity in the Scoring Rule Vindication of Probabilities
  16. No Place to Stand: The Incompleteness of All Calculi of Inductive Inference
  17. Infinite Lottery Machines
  18. Uncountable Problems
  19. Indeterministic Physical Systems
  20. A Quantum Inductive Logic
  21. Epilog
  22. Index

Contents

Prolog

1. The Material Theory of Induction Stated and Illustrated

Inductive inferences are not warranted by conformity with some universally applicable formal schema. They are warranted by background facts. The theory is illustrated with the help of Marie Curie’s inductive inference over the crystallographic properties of radium chloride.

2. What Powers Inductive Inference?

The principal arguments for the material theory are given. Any particular inductive inference can fail reliably if we try it in a world hostile to it. For an inference to be warranted, the world must be hospitable to it, and this is a contingent factual matter.

The material theory asserts that there are no universal rules of inductive inference. All induction is local. Chapters 3–9 will show how popular and apparently universal rules of inductive inference are defeasible and that their warrants in individual domains are best understood as deriving from particular background facts.

3. Replicability of Experiment

There is no universal inductive principle in science formulated in terms of replicability of experiment. Replication is not guaranteed to have inductive force. When it does, the force derives from background facts peculiar to the case at hand.

4. Analogy

Efforts to characterize good analogical inferences by their form have collapsed under the massive weight of the endless complexity needed to formulate a viable, general rule. For scientists, analogies are facts not argument forms, which fits nicely with the material view.

5. Epistemic Virtues and Epistemic Values: A Skeptical Critique

Talk of epistemic values in inductive inference misleads by suggesting that our preference for simpler theories is akin to a free choice, such as being a vegetarian. The better word is criterion, since these values are not freely chosen but must prove their mettle in guiding us to the truth.

6. Simplicity as a Surrogate

There is no viable principle that attaches simpler hypotheses to the truth. Appeals to simplicity are shortcuts that disguise more complicated appeals to background facts.

7. Simplicity in Model Selection

Statistical techniques, such as the Akaike Information Criterion (AIC), do not vindicate appeals to simplicity as a general principle. AIC depends on certain strong background assumptions independent of simplicity. We impose a simplicity interpretation on the formula it produces.

8. Inference to the Best Explanation: The General Account

There is no clearly defined relation of explanation that confers special inductive support on some hypotheses or theories. The important, canonical examples of inference to the best explanation can be accommodated better by simpler schemes involving background facts. The successful hypotheses or theories accommodate the evidence. The major burden in real cases in science is to show that competing accounts fail, either by contradicting the evidence or taking on burdensome evidential debt.

9. Inference to the Best Explanation: Examples

This chapter collects many examples from the history of science that illustrate the general claims of Chapter 8.

Chapters 10–16 address Bayesian confirmation theory, which has become the default account of inductive inference in philosophy of science, in spite of its weaknesses. Chapters 10, 11, and 12 address general issues. Chapters 13–16 display systems in which probabilistic representation of inductive strengths of support fails.

10. Why Not Bayes

While probabilistic analysis of inductive inference can be very successful in certain domains, it must fail as the universal logic of inductive inference. For an inductive logic must constrain systems beyond mere logical consistency. The resulting contingent restrictions will only obtain in some domains. Proofs of the necessity of probabilistic accounts fail since they require assumptions as strong as the result they seek to establish.

11. Circularity in the Scoring Rule Vindication of Probabilities

The scoring rule approach employs only the notion of accuracy and claims that probabilistic credences dominate. This chapter shows that accuracy provides little. The result really comes from an unjustified fine-tuning of the scoring rule to a predetermined result.

12. No Place to Stand: The Incompleteness of All Calculi of Inductive Inference

An inductively complete calculus of inductive inference can take the totality of evidential facts of science and, from them alone, determine the appropriate strengths of evidential support for the hypotheses and theories of science. This chapter reviews informally a proof given elsewhere that no calculus of inductive inference, probabilistic or not, can be complete.

13. Infinite Lottery Machines

An infinite lottery machine chooses among a countable infinity of outcomes without favor. While the example is used to impugn countable additivity, it actually also precludes even finite additivity.

14. Uncountable Problems

If we enlarge the outcome spaces to continuum size, we find further inductive problems that cannot be accommodated by a probabilistic logic. These include problems derived from the existence of metrically nonmeasuable sets.

15. Indeterministic Physical Systems

The indeterminism of a collection of indeterministic systems poses problems in inductive inference. They cannot be solved by representing strengths of inductive support as probabilities, unless one alters the problem posed.

16. A Quantum Inductive Logic

While the examples of Chapters 13–15 were simplified, this chapter proposes that there is a non-probabilistic inductive logic native to quantum mechanics.

Epilog

Index

Annotate

Next Chapter
Prolog
PreviousNext
©2021 John D. Norton
Powered by Manifold Scholarship. Learn more at
Opens in new tab or windowmanifoldapp.org